Medium : for amateurs |
This famous metaphor, attributed to Bernard de Chartres, a XIIth century philosopher, reused by Newton and Pascal among others, is a tribute to savant predecessors and an acknowledgment of the cumulative nature of scientific knowledge.
In this article, we will pay a tribute to Henri Poincaré, a brilliant mathematician, universal thinker and remarkable physicist. However, we will not try to grant him what is not his, but we will acknowledge some of his numerous contributions to the theory of relativity, which main idea is clearly owed to Albert Einstein.
Poincaré, forerunner of the principle of relativity
On September 14th of 1904, Henri Poincaré (1854-1912) gives a talk at the congress of arts and science in Saint-Louis, Missouri1, which title is The Principles of Mathematical Physics in which he defines :
« The principle of relativity, according to which the laws of physical phenomena must be the same for a stationary observer as for an observer carried along in a uniform motion of translation; so that we have not and can not have any means of discerning whether or not we are carried along in such a motion. » (Poincaré, 1904, p306)
Poincaré thus extends the relativity of motion to all laws of physics. However, we will see that the epistemological status of the principle is not that of a fundamental principle, but rather that of a common law of physics, verified (or otherwise unverified) by experimentation.
Indeed, the next year Poincaré publishes the paper The dynamics of electron, in which he remarks about the aether experiments, including that of Michelson which he refers to :
« It seems that this impossibility to disclose experimentally the absolute motion of the earth is a general law of nature; we are led naturally to admit this law, which we shall call the Postulate of Relativity, and to admit it unrestrictedly. Although this postulate, which up till now agrees with experiment, must be confirmed or disproved by later more precise experiments, it is in any case of interest to see what consequences can flow from it. »(Poincaré, 1905)
We clearly see in this quote that Poincaré considers the principle of relativity to be a law of nature, postulated not by logical necessity, but because the experiments suggest it. In Poincaré's view, the principle of relativity is the consequence of a dynamics he tries to identify (Damour, 2005), under the hypotheses of an electromagnetic origin of inertia and of all forces. He will do the same in a similar paper of 1908. Working on dynamics, he needs the concept of aether. Even if Poincaré believes that an absolute physical space does not exist, he sees the aether as a temporary but yet necessary construction of the mind, which goal is to simplify our representations. Hence he will always use the concept of aether in his work.
So his work is immersed in the electromagnetic theories of Maxwell, for whom « the existence of aether is a fundamental and undeniable fact of physics », Darrigol, 2005, p2) and of Lorentz (who works for example on an extension of electromagnetism wich would explain the gravitation) when he thinks about the possible electromagnetic origin of mass in 1908. Even if he is not looking for a theory of everything electromagnetic, Poincaré completely adheres to Maxwell's theory and does not question it, hence working in a very different context compared to that of Einstein.
Indeed, Poincaré is born in 1854 and finishes its education in 1878 (after Polytechnique, Ecole des Mines, in parallel to the Sorbonne). The theory of electromagnetism is then still quite new (Maxwell published its paper A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic Field in 1865) and Poincaré is the one who introduces it in France (Rougé, 2008, p29). So it is for him a thriving theory, already used by engineers even before he starts to teach it in 1887, and confirmed by Hertz's experiments, which he mentions in his class of 1890 (Rougé, 2008, p29). He knows the theory well, understands it and passes it onto the next generations. His thoughts about electrodynamics and the relativity principle have to fit into this well established body of knowledge. It it does not fit, if experiments disprove it, the principle shall be modified, or even be eliminated.
According to Poincaré, physics is in a period of crisis. He observes it, reports it, and makes suggestions, sometimes prophetic ones. M.A.Tonnelat quotes him :
« We shall, therefore, only have to hand over the matter to the experimenters, and, while waiting for them to finally decide the debate, not to preoccupy ourselves with these disquieting problems, and to tranquilly continue our work as if the principles were still uncontested. » (Poincaré, 1904, p616 of The Principles of Mathematical Physics)
And she concludes : « We see how much Poincaré's thinking disagrees with that of Einstein. The «crisis of relativity» is, in Poincaré's view, a purely experimental and probably only passing issue. » (Tonnelat, 1971, p123-124)
History of Lorentz transformations
Woldemart Voigt detects in 1887 (Ueber das Doppler'sche Princip, Göttinger Nachrichten, num. 7, p41-51, 1887) the invariance of some differential equations under the changes of coordinates (in modern terms) :
$x^\prime=x-vt$, $y^\prime=\frac y \gamma$, $z^\prime=\frac z\gamma$, $t^\prime=t-\frac{vx}{c^2}$, $\gamma=\frac1{\sqrt{1-\frac{v^2}{c^2}}}$
In 1889, George Francis FitzGerald (1851-1901) emits the hypothesis of a contraction of length (L'éther et l'atmosphère terrestre, Science, 1889) as will do, independently, Hendrik Antoon Lorentz (1853-1928) in 1892 (H.A.Lorentz, Die relative Bewegung der Erde und des Äthers, Zittingsverlag Akad. Wet. Amsterdam, vol. 1, p74, 1892).
In his book La théorie électromagnétique de Maxwell et son application aux corps mouvants (Archives Néerlandaises des sciences exactes et naturelles, T. XXV) of 1892, Lorentz will use different transformations than Voigt :
$x^\prime=\dfrac c{\sqrt{c^2-v^2}}x$, $y^\prime=y$, $z^\prime=z$, $t^\prime=t-\dfrac{\epsilon}{c}x^\prime$ with $\epsilon=\dfrac v{\sqrt{c^2-v^2}}$.
For Voigt as well as for Lorentz, these transformations still are only mathematical tools without any particular signification.
In an article of 1899 (Simplified Theory of Electrical and Optical Phenomena in Moving Systems, Proceedings of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences, vol. 1, p427-442, 1899), Lorentz will observe that the contraction hypothesis naturally flows from the transformations, which he'll modify :
$x^\prime=\dfrac c{\sqrt{c^2-v^2}}x$, $y^\prime=y$, $z^\prime=z$, $t^\prime=t-\dfrac{v}{c^2-v^2}x$
In a paper of 1904 (Electromagnetic phenomena in a system moving with any velocity smaller than that of light, Proceedings of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences, vol. 6, p809, 1904) Lorentz will give again different ones :
$x^\prime=klx$, $y^\prime=ly$, $z^\prime=lz$, $t^\prime=\frac lk t-kl\frac w{c^2}x$ with $k^2=\dfrac{c^2}{c^2-w^2}$
So we can clearly see that in 1904, the shape of these transformations is not fixed still, and will appear slowly, by trial and error.
The next year, 1905, Poincaré gives a talk at the Académie des Sciences, Sur la dynamique de l'électron which summarize the paper (Poincaré, 1905) he intends to present in Palermo, in which he confirms and corrects Lorentz's work of 1904, gives the corrected transformations their name
$x^\prime=kl(x+\epsilon t)$, $y^\prime=ly$, $z^\prime=lz$, $t^\prime=kl(t+\epsilon x)$ with $k=\dfrac 1{\sqrt{1-\epsilon^2}}$
and observes they must form a group :
So he gives them their definite shape 2 :
$x^\prime=k(x+\epsilon t)$, $y^\prime=y$, $z^\prime=z$, $t^\prime=k(t+\epsilon x)$ with $k=\dfrac 1{\sqrt{1-\epsilon^2}}$.
Einstein, founding father of a "super-law" (méta-loi)
Einstein is born in 1879 and studies at the Swiss Polytechnic Institute in Zurich, from 1896 to 1900. However, the lectures of his professor Heinrich Friedrich Weber (1843-1912) contains few if not any electromagnetism (Pais, 1993, p44 et p129) and is for him a lot less interesting than the modern book of August Föppl (1854- 1924) Einfürhung in die Maxwellsche Theorie der Elektrizität, Leipzig, Teubner, 1894, or Ernst Mach's book on mechanics (Pais, 1993, p44).
He also studies the work of a « supporter of Mach's philosophy » (Darrigol, 2005, p15), Paul Karl Ludwig Drude (1863-1906) with his book Physik des Aéthers, F. Enke, 1894.
So he learns electromagnetism by himself and is somewhat self-taught in modern physics. He does not depend on these ideas and builds his own point of view.
He also studies the work of a « supporter of Mach's philosophy » (Darrigol, 2005, p15), Paul Karl Ludwig Drude (1863-1906) with his book Physik des Aéthers, F. Enke, 1894.
So he learns electromagnetism by himself and is somewhat self-taught in modern physics. He does not depend on these ideas and builds his own point of view.
We've seen in the last post on Lorentz group Einstein's formulation of the principle of relativity, in his paper On the electrodynamics of moving bodies, and we can see that it is exactly equivalent to Poincaré's (let's remark that Einstein only knew of his book Science and hypothesis, 1902, at the time, and had no knowledge of the papers we mentioned above, see Pais, 1993).
But then, they still differ notably on three counts :- First of all, his motive is different. Einstein does not want to only correct Lorentz's theory, he rejects an asymmetry of Maxwell's theory in the induction effect, where a phenomenon receives two different explanations depending on the observer. It is this necessity of symmetry that justifies, in his view, the range of application of the principle of relativity to all of physics.
- Then, the epistemological status of the principle is fundamentally different than that of Poincaré :
Einstein sets a condition for the expression of all laws of physics.
If an equation or a postulate are not invariant under a Lorentz transformation, then the principle of relativity assures us that they are not laws of nature. Einstein sees the principle of relativity as a universal property, established as an axiom, it is a guide and the basis of the theory, a principle theory. It is a law about the physical laws, a super-law (méta-loi).
Moreover, the principle of relativity concerns space-time and gives to it a physical meaning even if this space is empty, baring no body (it is a kinematics, that is to say a condition for the expression of dynamics), wich Poincaré thinking about dynamics only could neither conceive, nor accept (Paty, 1987, p15).
This consideration only allows us to clearly differentiate the principle's roles in the work of Poincaré and Einstein.
To that, we have to add an important difference in style : Einstein constructs theories, with an axiomatic method, but Poincaré is merely a critic and suggests solutions, without ever building any complete theory, only presenting ideas historically (Rougé, 2008, p194).
- At last, since the principle tells us that there can be no privileged reference frame to describe the laws of physics, a mechanical aether is an aberration, in total logical contradiction with the theory. To try to keep it would force us to take away its only physical property standing : its immobility (Einstein, 1921, p84).
It is a concept that does not simplify anything according to Einstein, and is merely a source of contradiction, only causing problems without solving any.
Conclusion
We saw that it is Poincaré who names and formulates the principle of relativity, names and corrects Lorentz transformations, reports and exploits its group structure. To these examples, we could add that he establishes the method for synchronizing clocks by light signals (La mesure du temps, Revue de métaphysique et de morale, T.6, janv 1898), the formula of additivity of velocities, the invariance of Maxwell's equations in vacuum, and the hypothesis of the speed of light limit (Poincaré, 1905). Let's not forget that he also already uses a quadridmensional formalism that will inspire the future works of Minkowski, and then some. What is left ?
He clearly masters most of the concepts and technical tools of what we call now the special relativity theory, except (and it is fundamental !) that it is to him just corrections brought to Lorentz works, part of a dynamics, and what's more, depending upon Maxwell's electromagnetic theory.
That's what makes Einstein the real father of the theory, because he presents in his 1905 paper all of these points (except the importance of the group structure of Lorentz transformations) in a coherent theory, building a kinematics on which the laws of physics will depend (and not the other way around), including those of electromagnetism.
Still, Poincaré surely stays a great and major precursor amongst all physicists and mathematicians who played a role in the history of the theory of special relativity.
Notes :
1. During the 18th world fair, occurring from April 30th to December 1st of 1904.
2. The opposite signs mean only to consider the inverse transformations, without loss of generality.
Bibliography :
- Thibault Damour, Einstein 1905-1955 : son approche de la physique (FR), Séminaire Poincaré 1, p1-25, 2005.
- Olivier Darrigol, The genesis of the theory of relativity (EN), séminaire Poincaré, 2005.
- Albert Einstein, Ether and relativity (EN). Address delivered on May 5th, 1920, in the University of Leyden. Traduction française par Maurice Solovine, Gauthier-Villars, 1921.
- Abraham Pais, Subtle is the Lord: The Science and the Life of Albert Einstein (EN), Oxford University Press, 1983.
- Michel Paty, Einstein et la pensée de Newton (FR), La Pensée, num. 259, p17-37, 1987.
- Henri Poincaré, The Principles of Mathematical Physics (EN), p604 in Congress of arts and science (EN), universal exposition, St. Louis 1904, (1905), vol. 1, pp. 604-622. Also in The Value of Science (EN), 1913, New York: Science Press, Chap. 7-9, pp. 297-320.
- Henri Poincaré, La dynamique de l’électron (FR), Comptes Rendus des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences de Palerme, 1905.
Publication originale dans Rendiconti del Circolo Mathematico di Palermo, t.21, p129-175, 1906 (reçu le 23 juillet 1905, imprimé le 14 décembre 1905).
On the dynamics of electrons (excerpts) (EN), English translation by Scott Walter. For alternative translations see C. W. Kilmister Special Theory of Relativity, Oxford: Pergamon, 1970, p145-185; and H. M. Schwartz, American Journal of Physics 39:1287-1294; 40:862-872, 1282-1287.
See also H.M. Schwartz study in three parts, in the American Journal of Physics, (num.39 and 40, pages 1287–1294, 862–872, 1282–1287), Poincaré's rendiconti paper on relativity.
- Henri Poincaré, Sur la dynamique de l'électron (FR), note manuscrite, 5 juin 1905.
- André Rougé, Relativité Restreinte. La contribution d'Henri Poincaré (FR), Ecole polytechnique, 2008.
- Marie Antoinette Tonnelat, Histoire du principe de relativité (FR), Flammarion, Paris, 1971.
I agree with your assessment. I used to think that Poincare' had merely shown that one could come to the same mathematical conclusions as Lorentz by using rotational transformation to an imaginary axis representing a fourth dimension. It was in contrast to how Lorentz had used simple translation transformation using a conventional coordinate system and not adding an additional dimension. I was led to believe from writings elsewhere that Poincare', like Lorentz, did not make the physical connection between time and space. Those writings gave Einstein the credit for doing that.
Hi Larry,
Thanks for your comment.
Indeed, Poincare confirmed and gave credit to Lorentz's work, pushing its mathematical frame further afield.
As for the connection between time and space, for sure Einstein went deeper than both of them in that matter, but I believe Minkowski is probably the one who took it the furthest in special relativity (at least on the mathematical side, I'm not so sure for the physical aspect).
Cheers,
Johann.
PS : I like your blog, I'll certainly follow it.
You did not answer Jean question: why if he simply "perfected" the theory, he gets the credit for being the founder of the theory.
Originality is key even if it was a flawed originality! Further, nobody believes that Einstein did not know of Poincare's work! How could you work in the field of physics or any field and not know the leading lights! Come on! And you failed to report that Minkowski was popularizing HENRI POINCARE's work and Einstein was influenced by M. So we are to believe that Einstein didn't know the scientist that Minkowski was engaged with at that time.
You say stop stop fighting. No, let's continue because as Jean brilliantly points out, exposes your double standard: how in the hell can I be considered the father of something simply because I supposedly "perfected" it while presenting nothing fundamentally new or major that was different than the original theory but still claiming primary authorship! Get out of here and the world is catching on to double speak like this: The great genius here is HENRI POINCARE! He was not some obscure mathematician: this was a small, recognizable circle of scientists working on these problems so don't tell me that Mr. Plagiarist didn't know of Poincare's work.
Hi Russell,
You're quite right, I didn't answer Jean's question properly, sorry about that. Here's my answer :
I think the question of attribution depends on what you consider the core of the theory.
If it's only the principle of relativity alone, without any of its implications, then I understand why one would credit Poincaré as the founder of the theory. Because he saw before anyone else the need for this "renewed" principle.
BUT, he didn't build the theory. Sure he laid some grounds before Einstein. But Poincaré did not consider the principle of relativity as some kind of an axiom defining what a law of physics should be, and he didn't fully grasp its implications on space and time measurements (although he wasn't far from doing so). Einstein did. And it wasn't in a messy dozen of articles or so, but all condensed and clarified into one, that is rightfully so considered the founding article. So please stop saying that Einstein was "presenting nothing fundamentally new or major that was different than the original theory" because you're plain wrong. And also please, please stop calling Einstein a plagiarist, because it's a dishonor to science and history.
To respond to some of your arguments, first
you're right saying that Minkowski popularized Poincaré's work and influenced Einstein, but it was AFTER its <> Cologne lecture of 1908. And moreover, you're using the wrong arguments ! You could say that Einstein didn't grasp the 4 dimensionality of the theory before Minkowski and you would be right ! He even said to Minkowski that it was an unnecessary complication, and recognized only later when working on the generalized theory that he was wrong. So here you go, Minkowski also played a major role.
Second, you forget that Einstein did not live in an era of electronic instantaneous communication like nowadays when a scientist can know of a work just minutes after it's published. At the time of the 1900's, it could be years before you learned about even a major publication.
To conclude, I'd like to add that even if Einstein had read "La dynamique des électrons" (which I firmly believe he didn't, even if I can't prove it any more than you can prove he did), contrary to what you say his article did bring something fundamentally new and different than any previous work, including Poincaré's, namely 1° the concept of condition for the laws of physics, 2° the correct interpretation of space and time measurements and 3° A STRUCTURED AND CLEAN THEORY.
I suppose I didn't change your mind on the matter, but I hope you at least consider the possibility that I could be right as strongly as I consider the possibility that you could be right. Matters of science can be decided with proof, while unfortunately matters of history can sometimes be very much harder to definitely conclude... and that makes me sad.
Have a nice day.
Cheers,
Johann.